In 1900 Ivar Fredholm presented a method for the solution of integral equations. The method was extremely useful in showing the existence of solutions for certain types of boundary-value problems in partial differential equations, and attracted a good deal of international attention. There were two main lines of reception of the work. The more conservative consisted of detailed investigations of its meaning in the field of differential equations, with important contributions by Poincaré, Picard, T. Boggio and G. Lauricella, among others. The more radical was initiated by Hilbert, and lies at the origin of the theory of linear operators on what we now term Hilbert spaces. In this paper we examine these two threads in the early reception of Fredholm's work, which persisted as separate though interacting traditions.
I will discuss the philosophical implications of my work in experimental mathematics. Philosophers have frequently distinguished mathematics from the physical sciences. While the sciences were constrained to fit themselves via experimentation to the `real' world, mathematicians were allowed more or less free reign within the abstract world of the mind. This picture has served mathematicians well for the past few millennia but the computer has begun to change this. The computer has given us the ability to look at new and unimaginably vast worlds. It has created mathematical worlds that would have remained inaccessible to the unaided human mind, but this access has come at a price. Many of these worlds, at present and perhaps for ever, can only be known experimentally. Thus, work in experimental mathematics challenges the standard view of mathematics as a subject in which proof is the sole pathway to knowledge.
David Bailey and I make this case at length in our newly published books on Experimental Mathematics (www.expmath.info). We start by observing that: One of the greatest ironies of the information technology revolution is that while the computer was conceived and born in the field of pure mathematics, through the genius of giants such as John von Neumann and Alan Turing, until recently this marvelous technology had only a minor impact within the field that gave it birth.
The future of mathematical computing is expected to rely on a mixture of symbolic and numeric (hybrid) computation that will increasingly call for significant computing power. This is obvious at the level of "grand challenge problems" in fluid dynamics, meteorology and elsewhere, but is equally true in the finance and banking sectors, as for e-commerce and, growingly, for pure mathematics. Indeed, it is my personal conviction that the success of the computer as an inference assistant and insight generating engine demands massively parallel computation. Only when many small things are done by the computer on a real time scale (as the mathematical equivalent of a "spell-checker") can insight follow easily and freely.
En donnant à l'algèbre son indépendance face à l'arithmétique et à la géométrie et en la situant dans le cadre d'un programme analytique, au sens des Anciens, Viète ouvre de nouvelles perspectives en mathématiques. Mais l'oeuvre du pionnier est reçue de diverses façons par les mathématiciens qui lui succèdent. Nous verrons comment progressivement la pensée viètienne est appliquée dans les travaux de ses premiers disciples, Anderson et Ghetaldi, de reconstructions d'oeuvres grecques perdues, mais aussi de disciples plus tardifs, aujourd'hui oubliés, comme James Hume, Pierre Herigone et Nicolas Durret. Leurs oeuvres illustrent le passage graduel de l'algèbre dite vulgaire à une algèbre qui nous est plus familière, comme celle de Descartes et des autres grands mathématiciens de la fin du siècle.
The archives for the Bourbaki group have been recently enlarged and expanded. They may be broadly divided into two categories:
In December and January of 1983-1984, archaeologists excavating the tomb of an ancient Chinese nobleman at a Western Han Dynasty site near Zhangjiashan, in Jiangling county, Hubei Province, discovered a number of books on bamboo strips, including works on legal statutes, military practice, and medicine. Among these was a previously unknown mathematical work on some 200 bamboo strips, the Suan Shu Shu, or Book of Numbers and Computation. As the earliest yet discovered work devoted specifically to mathematics from ancient China (no later than 186 BCE), it has stirred considerable interest among historians of Chinese mathematics.
While some sections of this work are straightforward and have been understood with little disagreement, others-whether because of missing, misplaced, or incomplete parts of the texts on the bamboo strips comprising this earliest of the yet-known mathematical works from ancient China-have been open to diverse and often divergent interpretations. In some cases, related methods serve as clues to help interpret the meaning of given problems, as is the case for the three problems devoted to Fu Tan, Lu Tang, and Yu Shi. But for another pair of seemingly related problems, Yi Yuan Cai Fang and Yi Fang Cai Yuan, there has been little agreement about whether these are inverse or quite different problems, and virtually everyone who has approached these two problems has understood them differently in trying to account for the statements, answers, and methods given for these two problems. This presentation will be devoted to discussion of the various collations and explanations offered for these especially challenging parts of the Suan Shu Shu, and what they may tell us about early Chinese mathematics in general.
When many of the parents of today's high school students were themselves in high school, the slide rule was ubiquitous: mysterious to many, but as iconic a badge of the scientist as the doctor's stethoscope or the farmer's pitchfork. Today, three decades later, not a single one of the famous brands-Keufel and Esser, Hemmi, Faber and Castell, etc.-are still manufactured. For the inflation-adjusted cost of a basic slide rule in 1970, you can buy a calculator which can do everything that the slide rule could, and much more. Moreover, the calculator is easy enough to use that it has achieved a level of penetration into the schoolroom that the slide rule never did.
Nonetheless, it can be argued that the slide rule had pedagogical potentials that the calculator-no matter how sophisticated-does not. It makes many of the properties of exponents and logarithms clear in an intuitive, tactile way. It encourages order-of-magnitude calculation and provides a good motivation for scientific notation. And, finally, it is today a link with living mathematical history; for some decades yet, many school classes will be able to find a parent or grandparent who used a slide rule professionally.
This talk suggests some ways in which the slide rule might be included in the modern high school classroom. In particular, I will look briefly at ways of getting around the current (and, it is to be feared, continuing) slide rule shortage, and some ways in which the design of the slide rule might be modified for an environment in which it is primarily a manipulative rather than a calculating device.
For the past 6 years I have presented conferences to groups of liberal art students whose formation includes no maths and no science beyond high school. They are students in a specific 1 year program called "Odyssée Humaine" in which all the different classes are interrelated, that is the teacher in a philosophy class for instance knows exactly where the students are in their geography or history class and builds his own course upon this knowledge.
We are in the process of creating a specific course on History of Maths and Science that will be integrated into a modified version of l'Odyssée Humaine that is supposed to begin in September 2005. Of course, it will probably take a few years to create a satisfactory description of this course. Nevertheless, it starts next September and in this talk, I'll present the starting point of my thoughts concerning this presentation of Math History to non-scientists.
One of the important difference between this course and a similar course that is intended for math students is the objective. Knowledge of specific results is not an important part of this new course, but the integration of mathematical knowledge and scientific knowledge in the broader scope of the evolution of the western culture is.
Two examples: First, Mathematics in Ancient Greece probably played an important rôle in the apparition of Greek rationalism and philosophy. Second, new successes in maths, applied as well as pure, played an important part of the fast evolution of Europe after the Middle Ages. Just knowing that they were able to do things that the Ancient Greeks and Romans never did was enough to create a climate of confidence that lead to the scientific revolution of the 17th century.
Many of us were drawn to topological dynamics in the 1970s and 1980s by the apparently surprising behavior and broad applicability of maps of the unit interval: a sequence of bifurcations leading to the onset of chaos showing apparently random behavior. At the same time, many key results are readily accessible to undergraduate students, and topological dynamics has found its way into the undergraduate curriculum. This talk will survey some high points of historical development of topological dynamics.
Partially supported by the NSF.
Thomas Simpson (1710-1761) was a self-taught English mathematician who wrote several remarkable books, among them "The Doctrine and Application of Fluxions" (1750). The fact that in 1823 it was still being published attests to its wide and deserved popularity. Changing the word "fluxion" by "derivative", the problems on maxima and minima that can be found in the above-mentioned work stand out as particularly interesting and can be read with profit nowadays. Keeping a historical framework we will discuss some of these problems.
A survey of early computability theory will be presented. Here, "early" means the 1920s and 1930s. The main different, but equivalent, approaches to formalizing (or defining) the notion of effective calculability in this period will be discussed, as will be the motivations of the prime movers of the theory, including Gödel, Kleene, Church, Turing and Post. Modern continuations of some research threads originating in the early period will be briefly discussed.
Ptolemy's treatise on celestial mechanics, the Almagest, is not composed as an assemblage of reasonings but as a single reasoning, the biggest deductive argument in all ancient applied mathematics. This is exceptional in the history of astronomical writing, even (so far as we can tell) in antiquity. Other writers recognize that the solutions of some problems depend on others, but they generally assume that some degree of isolation between problems is possible. But for Ptolemy, mathematical astronomy is like a puzzle that can only be taken apart piece by piece in a particular order starting with a particular key piece.
This paper will consider three aspects of the logical structure of the Almagest:
It is a remarkable fact that Einstein and Hilbert discovered the field equations of the relativistic theory of gravitation almost simultaneously, following totally different paths. I shall review some of the highlights of this fascinating episode, including the important contribution that Emmy Noether made to the development of Hilbert's approach.
Categorial grammar is an attempt to place most of the grammar of a natural language into the dictionary. This is accomplished by assigning to each word in the dictionary one or more types, which are taken to be elements of an algebraic system or terms of a substructural logic. There are, at present, two streams of investigation. One, going back to Ajdukiewicz, relies on residuated monoids, i.e., monoids equipped with two binary operations of division that mimic logical implication. The other makes use of two unary operations instead, which mimic the logical operation of negation. It turns out that the second approach, which I now favour, has historical roots in ideas of C. S. Peirce and Z. Harris.
We trace the development of the ideas of multiplication in Mesopotamia from the first archaic evidence to the Old Babylonian period (2000-1600 BC). In particular, we will show how the abstract sexagesimal place value system that was developed at the end of the third millennium allowed the unification of ideas of area and repeated addition by freeing these concepts from the metrological systems that had earlier been in use.
The modelling of an important number of problems in mathematics leads to real systems of equations with real unknowns. Depending on the context we may only be interested in the number of solutions, or the subproblems of, either finding a bound for the number of solutions, or showing that the number of solutions are finite. In this lecture I will discuss the power of Rolles theorem and its generalization by Khovanskii to the Rolles theorem for dynamical systems. I will introduce the theory of fewnomials and discuss some applications.
The bulk of Heron's Measurements can be described as applied, perhaps even practical, mathematics. In the third book, however, he gives a series of analytic propositions in the pure geometric idiom. He tells us that these will be useful for solving problems which cannot be solved by computation (dia ton arithmon). An investigation of this material is interesting on two counts. In the first place, it adds to our limited evidence for the actual practice of ancient geometrical analysis. More interestingly, however, it makes clear that Heron considered geometrical analysis capable of solving certain problems that were not susceptible to computation. My talk will try to elucidate Heron's thinking in these matters.
The 12th-century mathematician Ibn Yahya al-Maghribi al-Samaw'al, now better known for his algebra, also wrote the extensive treatise Exposure of the Errors of the Astronomers. This fascinating under-studied work, containing criticisms of a number of astronomers, provides an interesting study of debates over the proper practice of medieval astronomy. In particular, al-Samaw'al eschews any form of geometrical approximation, no matter how trivial. One of his objections is to the methods that had been used to determine the geometrically unattainable sin (1 degree), in Ptolemy's Almagest as well as in later Muslim works. To avoid this apparently unavoidable problem, al-Samaw'al presents an alternate trigonometric table that breaks the circle into 480 rather than 360 parts. We shall present the table as well as one of its uses in al-Samaw'al's work.
The history of traditional Vietnamese mathematics can be reconstructed on the basis of the extant mathematical treatises only partially. Some 20 mathematical treatises are to be found in Vietnamese libraries, of which the latest ones were compiled in the early 20th century; as for the earliest texts, the date of their actual compilation remains uncertain, but most likely they do not antedate the early 18th century. All these texts are compiled on the basis of Chinese mathematical treatises of the Ming (1368-1644) and Qing (1644-1911) dynasties.
The paper will focus on several issues pertaining to the study: