|
|
|
|
|
History of Mathematics at the Dawn of a New Millennium / L'histoire
des
mathématiques à l'aube d'un nouveau millénaire (Tom Archibald, Organizer)
- FRANCINE ABELES, Kean University, Union, New Jersey, USA
Game theory and politics: a note on C. L. Dodgson
-
In 1884, C. L. Dodgson wrote The Principles of Parliamentary
Representation where he showed, for the first time, that in an
election if each of two political parties utilizes a maximin strategy
in a two person zero sum game model, the result would be a ``best''
electoral system in the sense of providing the greatest degree of voter
representation.
- AMY ACKERBERG-HASTINGS, Iowa State University, Iowa, USA
The semi-secret history of Charles Davies
-
Charles Davies (1798-1876) and his textbooks invariably show up in
discussions touching on mathematics education in the United States in
the nineteenth century. Yet, due to the generality, age, or
inaccessibility of most of even the relevant secondary sources, many
mathematicians and historians have been unable to learn the reasons why
Davies exerted such a pervasive influence. Thus, this paper draws upon
the first modern biography of Davies to outline his life and career.
The paper will also note some of the perennial themes in mathematics
education manifested in Davies' textbook series.
- CHRISTOPHER BALTUS, State University of New York, Oswego, New York, USA
Gauss's algebraic proof of the fundamental theorem of algebra
-
Gauss offered a second proof of the Fundamental Theorem of Algebra,
some years after his 1799 proof, resting on `purely analytic
principles'-we would now call it algebraic-but avoiding the
fundamental defect of previous proofs, the `supposition that the
function can be resolved into simple factors.' Gauss's argument has
been interpreted in a variety of ways, including the claim by
Bachmacova (1960) that he created a field of decomposition for the
polynomial along lines that Kronecker would later follow. I propose to
simply reexamine Gauss's original argument, in its original context.
- EDWARD COHEN, University of Ottawa, Ottawa, Ontario
The leap-year problem has not gone away
-
In Julius Caesar's time (45BCE), it was thought that the length of a
year was 365 1/4 days; i.e., Caesar made one leap year every 4
years or 100 years in 400 years. Pope Gregory XIII in 1582 changed
that to 97 years in 400 years because the astronomers in his time had a
more accurate picture of how long a period it took for the earth to go
around the sun. This is more precise; however, in the year 2000CE, the
Gregorian calendar overstates the length of the year by approximately
26 seconds. This means that in approximately 1582 + 3330 years, we
would have to drop one leap year. Also, the length of the solar year
is not a constant. This further complicates the situation. One of the
first astronomers to consider the leap-year problem was Simon Newcomb
(1835-1909). We try to state the problem as he saw it and consider
how it might be solved.
- TOM DRUCKER, Modern Logic Inc.
Language, truth, and logic in Russell's mathematics
-
Bertrand Russell's distaste for ordinary language philosophy was often
expressed, and he sought a language with which to express mathematics
in an incorrigible fashion. This talk will look at Russell's idea of
mathematical truth in the first decade of the 1900's and the forms of
linguistic expression this truth could take. His views will be viewed
against the background of the algebraic tradition in logic as well as
the subsequent model-theoretic lines of research.
- CRAIG FRASER, University of Toronto
Hilbert's Grundlagen der geometrie and its relation to Euclid's
elements
-
Hilbert's Grundlagen der Geometrie (1899) is widely regarded as a
canonical work of modern mathematics. Howard Eves and Carroll V. Newson
write, ``By developing a postulate set for plane and solid geometry
that does not depart too greatly in spirit from Euclid's own, and by
employing a minimum of symbolism, Hilbert succeeded in convincing
mathematicians, to a far greater extent than had Pasch and Peano, of
the purely hypothetico-deductive nature of geometry'' (Foundations and
Fundamental Concepts of Mathematics (1966, p. 94), my emphasis). The
origins and historical influence of Hilbert's book have been explored
in the writings of Michael Toepell and Leo Corry. The purpose of the
present paper is to provide a comparative study of the Grundlagen and
Elements I-VI in order to elucidate points of similarity and difference
in approach, concept and outlook between the two works. The paper also
explores the meaning of deduction in the modern mathematical
tradition.
- ROGER GODARD, Royal Military College
Interpolation theory at the dawn of a new millennium: an
historical approach
-
This paper comments on the old interpolation problem, and particularly,
the contribution of the twentieth century. However, we shall start our
study with Lagrange (1792-1793). Here we emphasize the mathematical,
numerical, and philosophical problems, and the evolution of proofs
linked to interpolation. After the discovery of the Runge phenomenon
(1901), the problem of approximation of equidistant data by polynomials
was better understood (de la Vallée-Poussin, Bernstein, Montel). In
this work, we also present trigonometric interpolation, which
represents efforts towards the development of orthogonal functions and
generalized Fourier series, and certain classes of functions, which
can't be developed in Taylor's series. We reexamine the tools of the
Fourier transform in the interpolation theory, and the sampling theorem
(Wiener, 1934; J. M. Whittaker, 1935; Shannon, 1950) which is also a
global interpolation formula. Schoenberg (1946) tried to divide the
problem of interpolation into two categories. He distinguished the
case where the ordinates belong to known analytical functions and the
case where the ordinates come from empirical observations. In the
later case, he suggested the spline interpolation.
This truly empirical approach was to be extremely fruitful for the
Theory of Approximation, Schoenberg did not realize that he transformed
the problem of interpolation into a problem of linear algebra, where
the results are obtained by the numerical solution of a sparse system
of linear equations, which is very stable.
- HARDY GRANT, York University, York, Ontario
Greek mathematics in cultural context
-
In classic Greece the claims of various pursuits, including
mathematics, to the status of an ``art'' or a ``science'', with the
attendant prestige, were much in the air. I shall try to set
mathematics in this context by considering its possible influences on,
and influences from, its rivals in the competition-two such rivals in
particular.
- NICHOLAS GRIFFIN, McMaster University
Russell's logicism is not `If-Thenism'
-
At the beginning of Principles of Mathematics Russell defines pure
mathematics in terms of a special set of conditional statements. This
remark, together with other things he says about geometry and rational
mechanics, have led many people to suppose that his logicism is a type
of ``if-thenism''-that is, that the theses of his logicism are all of
the form ``if p then q'' where p is a logical axiom and q a
mathematical theorem. I show that this is not the case and that the
conditional form that Russell insists on at the beginning of the
Principles is imposed for quite different reasons, having to do with
the unrestricted nature of the variables.
- AGNES KALEMARIS, SUNY Farmingdale, Farmingdale, New York, USA
Grace Murray Hopper was a mathematician
-
Grace Murray Hopper (1906-1992) had justly received recognition for
her pioneering work in computer science. However, she began her career
as a mathematician, earning a bachelor's degree in mathematics and
physics at Vassar in 1928, and a masters and Ph.D. at Yale in 1930 and
1934, respectively. This paper will discuss some of her
accomplishments in mathematics and her unconventional methods of
teaching it.
- ISRAEL KLEINER, York University, York, Ontario
Aspects of the evolution of field theory
-
I will discuss highlights of the evolution of field theory, including
some of its sources and its emergence as a mature, abstract theory.
- ERWIN KREYSZIG, Carleton University, Ottawa
``Modern'' starts
-
This paper concerns the roots and the early period of ``modern
mathematics'', a short term for the mathematics of the twentieth
century, as opposed to the ``classical mathematics'' of the nineteenth
century. It explores the principal reasons for the main differences of
modern mathematics from classical, in both form and content. This
includes advances in formalization, axiomatization, and the emphasis of
structures, as well as the appearance of totally new areas, mainly
topology (general as well as algebraic), functional analysis and
algebra (as in van der Waerden's classic and beyond). We shall
concentrate on the first two of these three areas and show their
closely related evolution, whose systematic beginnings are usually
considered to be marked by Volterra's work on special functionals in
1887, Poincare's introduction of combinatorial complexes in 1895, and
Frechet's and F. Riesz's (independent) works on abstract spaces in
1906. It will be shown that the period from 1880 to 1915 (roughly) had
transitional character in the sense that areas and their problems,
mainly in the calculus of variations, spectral theory, and integral
equations, that motivated and paved the way in functional analysis,
were developed by means of classical analysis.
The title of the paper is borrowed from a contemporary exhibition in
the Museum of Modern Art in New York City, and the paper will be
concluded with a few comparative remarks on analogies and differences.
- SHARON KUNOFF, C.W. Post Campus, Long Island University, New York, USA
A commentary on the first Hebrew geometry and its relationship
to the first arabic geometry
-
In 1932 Solomon Gandz published a version of the Mishnat Ha Middot
containing a fragment which had recently come to light. This new data
enabled him to date the text c. 150. The Geometry of Al-Khowarizmi C.
820 contains much of the same facts, with some additions. In this paper
we will look at some material from each and compare the results. We
will also consider the practical nature of the material, seeing how it
was written to demonstrate how to do various geometric computations,
rather than as a theoretical theorem-proof geometry.
- GREGORY LAVERS, University of Western Ontario
Gödel, Carnap and Friedman on analyticity
-
Michael Friedman, in his paper ``Analyticity and Logical syntax: Carnap
vs. Gödel'', admits that his previous argument concerning the success
of Carnap's project in The LogicalSyntax of Language was mistaken. He
admits, as well, that although he developed this argument independently
it is essentially the same argument that Gdel put forward in the paper
that he wrote for, but was not included in the Schlipp volume on
Carnap. However, he maintains that the Gdelean argument, although not
in itself fatal to Carnap's program, can be used to point out what is
viciously circular in this program. In this paper I show that Gdel's
argument does point to a flaw in Carnap's project, if one is willing to
accept Gdel somewhat mystical presuppositions. I then show that
Friedman's case against Carnap, which can be seen as a demystification
of Gdel's argument fails to address Carnap.
- DAVID LAVERTY, University of Western Ontario
Kit Fine's theory of variable objects and his
-
In his Cantorian Abstraction: A Reconstruction and Defense, Kit Fine
argues that if we treat the units resulting from a Cantorian
abstraction as `variable objects' we avoid the traditional problems
associated with Cantorian abstraction and we are left with an account
of number which rivals the competing accounts of Zermelo/von Neumann on
one side, and Frege/Russell on another. According to Fine, the
Zermelo/von Neumann account has the advantage of being
representational, but suffers from being arbitrary, whereas the
Frege/Russell account, while not being arbitrary, nonetheless is not
representational. Fines reconstruction of Cantor, however, provides us
with an account that combines both advantages. We are given an account
of number that is both representational and nonarbitrary. In this
paper, I argue that the benefits gained from a representational account
are, however, greatly outweighed by the costs involved in adopting
Fines Theory of Variable Objects.
- DARYN LEHOUX, University of Toronto
The Zodiacal days in the Geminus and Miletus parapegmata
-
The Geminus and ``Miletus I'' parapegmata are astronomical instruments
that give day-by-day predictions for the annual risings and settings of
the fixed stars. In the Geminus parapegma these stellar `phases' are
tied to daily weather predictions as well. In both parapegmata the
stellar phases are organized according to the sun's motion through the
zodiac. Thus, for example, Geminus has ``On the first day of Leo,
Sirius appears, according to Euctemon; the hot weather begins.'' The
zodiacal days (``first day of Leo, second day of Leo,'' etc.)
have been interpreted as betraying the existence of a special Greek
(astronomical) zodiacal calendar. I will argue that this interpretation
is untenable. Instead we should see the zodiacal days as being a kind
of extra-calendrical calibration mechanism for these instruments,
which would allow the Greeks to use the same parapegma from year to
year and in different cities, in spite of the vagaries of the various
observational lunar calendars in use.
- ALBERT LEWIS, Indiana University, Indiana, USA
The contrasting views of Charles S. Peirce and Bertrand
Russell on Cantor's transfinite paradise
-
Russell and Peirce were opposites in many ways, but both saw great
philosophical significance in Georg Cantor's theory of transfinite
numbers. Russell thought Cantor's notions invalid at first but by 1900
came to unreserved acceptance of them. Peirce, the American pragmatist,
in the same year more readily accepted their mathematical validity but
regarded them as products of a curtailed view of the continuum. Is it
possible a century later to evaluate which view has better stood the
test of time?
- HUGH MCCAGUE, York University, York, Ontario
The mathematics of building and analysing a medieval cathedral
-
The designing and building of a medieval cathedral applied mathematics
in a variety of ways. The main application was practical geometry. A
master mason could adeptly and repeatedly apply a few simple geometric
tools and operations to produce a myriad of sophisticated designs as
attested by the cathedrals themselves, by extant late medieval design
manuscripts, and by full-scale drawings still etched on church floors
and walls. Another applied mathematical element that worked hand in
hand with the geometry was the use of measurement units, such as the
English royal foot and perch. The rediscovery of the mathematical
schema employed at a specific church, such as Durham Cathedral, is a
challenging problem within architectural history. This issue is
beginning to get much needed assistance from recent statistical methods
including circular data analysis and bootstrapping techniques. The
meaning and symbolism of the cathedral also applied mathematics through
such means as the mathematical schema of the Heavenly Jerusalem which
was the key dedicatory identification for the church. Further,
stonemasonry was reverently known as the Art of Geometry, and was one
of the mechanical arts which in complement with the liberals arts
formed the means for the human's attainment of wisdom. Like Creation,
the building of a medieval cathedral was to follow the law of Wisdom
11:21: ``Thou madest all things in measure, number and weight.''
- DUNCAN MELVILLE, St. Lawrence University
Third millennium mathematics: A brief survey
-
While many people are aware of the origins of mathematics in tokens
in the Near East and its flowering into a powerful technical
discipline in the Old Babylonian period, few except specialists
study the history linking these two points. In this talk, we shall
give a brief survey of how mathematics developed in the crucial
third millennium. We will pay particular attention to the
development of cuneiform and the famous place-value sexagesimal
system of scientific computation.
- MIKE MILLAR, Northern Iowa
-
- GREGORY MOORE, McMaster University
Editing mathematicians: Bertrand Russell and Kurt Goedel
-
This talk discusses editing the collected papers of the two
mathematicians mentioned above (both of whom were philosophers as
well), particularly in regard to their mathematical logic. Questions
as to what unpublished materials to include in the respective volumes
are central to this talk. In Russell's case, the use of his evolving
logical symbolism in dating previously undated manuscripts and in
determining which order manuscripts were composed will be treated in
some detail. The speaker was one of six editors for two volumes of
Goedel's works, has previously published one volume of Russell's and is
now completing a second. For the two Russell volumes, he is the sole
editor.
- RAM MURTY, Queen's University
Euclid, Brahmagupta, and ABC
-
The purpose is to survey the problem of finding integer solutions
(x,y) for axn + byn = 1 with a,b given integers. Of course, for
n = 1, this is Euclid (c. 300 B.C.). For n = 2, it is Brahmagupta (c.
600 A.D.) and for larger n, one needs the ABC conjecture of Masser
and Oesterle (1980 A.D.) to solve it effectively. (In the latter case,
there are only finitely many solutions.)
- ADRIAN RICE, Randolph-Macon College
-
- ARIANE ROBITAILLE, Université de Nantes, France
Can we learn something about combinatorics from review journals?
-
Mathematical review journals, such as Mathematical Reviews and
Zentralblatt für Mathematik und ihre Grenzgebiete, are full of clues
helping us to put in a global perspective a particular mathematical
subject seen as a whole within Mathematics. We can do a quantitative
analysis of the number of articles published about the subject, look
where those articles have been published, scrutinize the evolution of
the classification systems used, etc. Armed with all that
material, we can establish a tentative periodization that will need a
deeper look, and we can make a comparison with the rest of mathematics.
In my talk, I will discuss my work done with review journals in the
case of combinatorics.
- DONNA SPRAGGON, McMaster University
Felix Klein's ``Erlanger programm'' and its influence
-
Acting on his belief that the study of geometry had become too
fragmented, Klein distributed his bold exposition Vergleichende
Betrachtung ueber neuere geometrische Forschungen on December 17,
1872 at his inaugural address at Friedrich-Alexander-Universitaet in
Erlangen, Germany. This pamphlet suggested that the use of algebra, or
more specifically the group theory of the time, to classify all of the
known geometries. The influence of the contents, more commonly
referred to as the Erlanger Programm (EP), has been subject to
debate by many historians of mathematics. Although Klein's unifying
concept had not been developed to its full potential, one may gain an
appreciation for its significance. To this end, it is necessary to
approach the analysis of the influence in several different ways. We
will examine the years 1872-1889, the influx of republications of the
EP, the effects on the Italian School of geometry, Riemannian geometry,
Relativity theory and the influence on the teaching of geometry. In
considering these factors, this paper exposes a clear, yet complex,
look at the influence of Felix Klein's Erlanger Programm.
- JIM TATTERSALL, Providence College
Vignettes from Gerbert's mathematics
-
Gerbert d'Aurillac (940-1003) distinguished himself as scholar,
mathematician, and cleric. He was an avid proponent of the Hindu-Arabic
system. We investigate several interesting geometric and number
theoretic problems proposed in his treatises and correspondence.
- RUDIGER THIELE, University of Leipzig, Germany
On Hilbert's 24th problem
-
At the end of the year 1899 David Hilbert was invited to make one of
the major addresses at the second International Congress of
Mathematicians in August 1900 in Paris. Hilbert hesitated and at last
decided to lecture on some open mathematical problems, but he decided
so late (in July) that his talk ``Mathematical Problems'' was only
included in the History section instead of the opening session.
However, Hilbert's problems have proved to be central in the 20th
century and became famous. All in all he discussed 23 important
problems, although he did not present all of them in his address.
Furthermore, he had even cancelled a problem on proof theory. The talk
will give a short prehistory of Hilbert's famous talk and then a short
overview of the problems Hilbert published in the Proceedings. I will
go into some detail on the 23rd problem and on the (cancelled) 24th
problem.
- ROBERT THOMAS, University of Manitoba, Winnipeg, Manitoba, R3T 2N2
Mathematics and fiction: A pedagogical comparison
-
Mathematics is often compared to music and poetry. Another comparison
is presented here, that to simple stories. Most persons do not write
either music or poetry, have no idea how, but do tell stories. Perhaps
this comparison can help those not willing or able to learn mathematics
to appreciate some of how the art of mathematics is practised.
- GLEN VAN BRUMMELEN, Bennington College
sin 10: From Ptolemy to al-Kashi
-
Trigonometric tables were fundamental to the work of practicing
astronomers from Hipparchus onward; poorly-computed values could
compromise almost all predictions of the positions of the heavenly
bodies. Geometric considerations permit the computation of 1/3 of the
values in a typical sine table; a good estimate of sin 10 is needed to
determine the remaining sines. Ptolemy's estimate of the (almost
equivalent) chord of 10 in the Almagest is well-known; Jamshid
al-Kashi's early 15th-century iterative scheme is almost as famous. We
shall emphasize intervening accomplishments, including the history
behind al-Kashi's little-known original method and its eventual use in
Ulugh Beg's monumental sine table. Other techniques that might have
been used to generate the thousands of entries in these tables will be
presented. This paper represents joint work with two undergraduate
researchers: Abe Buckingham (The King's University College) and Micah
Leamer (Bennington College).
|
|